Do Drugs Have Religious Import?
Huston Smith, Ph.D.
©The Journal of Philosophy, Vol LXI, No.
18, September 17, 1964
Until six months ago, if I picked up my phone in the Cambridge
area and dialed KISS-BIG a voice would answer, "Ifif." These were coincidences:
KISS-BIG simply happened to be the letter equivalents of an arbitrarily assigned
telephone number, while I.F.I.F. represented the initials of an organization
with the improbable name of the International Federation for Internal Freedom.
But the coincidences were apposite to the point of being poetic. "Kiss big"
caught the euphoric, manic, life-embracing attitude that characterized this most
publicized of the organizations formed to explore the newly synthesized
consciousness-changing substances, while the organization itself was surely one
of the "iffy-est" phenomena to appear on our social and intellectual scene in
some time. It produced the first firings in Harvard's history, an ultimatum to
get out of Mexico in five days, and "the miracle of Marsh Chapel" in which
during a two-and-one-half hour Good Friday service ten theological students and
professors ingested psilocybin and were visited by what they generally reported
to be the deepest religious experiences of their lives.
Despite the last of these phenomena and its numerous if less dramatic parallels,
students of religion appear by and large to be dismissing the psychedelic drugs
which have sprung to our attention in the sixties as having little religious
relevance. The position taken in one of the most forward-looking volumes of
theological essays to have appeared in recent years (1)
accepts R. C. Zaehner's Mysticism Sacred and Profane as having "fully
examined and refuted" the religious claims for mescaline which Aldous Huxley
sketched in The Doors of Perception. This closing of the case strikes me
as premature, for it looks as if the drugs have light to throw on the history of
religion, the phenomenology of religion, the philosophy of religion, and the
practice of the religious life itself.
1. Drugs and Religion Viewed Historically
In his
trial-and-error life explorations man almost everywhere has stumbled upon
connections between vegetables (eaten or brewed) and actions (yogic breathing
exercises, whirling dervish dances, flagellations) which altered states of
consciousness. From the psychopharmacological standpoint we now understand these
states to be the products of changes in brain chemistry. From the sociological
perspective we see that they tended to be connected in some way with religion.
If we discount the wine used in our own communion services, the instances
closest to us in time and space are the peyote of The Native American (Indian)
Church and Mexico's 2,000-year-old "sacred mushrooms," the latter rendered in
Aztec as "God's flesh" striking parallel to "the body of our Lord" in the
Christian Eucharist. Beyond these neighboring instances lie the soma of
the Hindus, the haoma and hemp, identical with and better known as
marijuana, of the Zoroastrians, the Dionysus of the Greeks who "everywhere.. .
taught men the culture of the vine and the mysteries of his worship and
everywhere [was] accepted as a god," (2)
the benzoin of Southeast Asia, Zen's tea whose fifth cup purifies and
whose sixth "calls to the realm of the immortals," (3) the
pituri of the Australian aborigines and probably the mystic kykeon
that was eaten and drunk at the climactic close of the sixth day of the
Eleusinian mysteries. (4)
There is no need to extend the list, especially as Philippie de Felice's
comprehensive study of the subject, Poisons Sacrés, Ivresses Divines (Sacred
Poisons, Divine Raptures), is about to appear in English.
More interesting than the fact that consciousness-changing devices have been
linked with religion is the possibility that they actually initiated many of the
religious perspectives which, taking root in history, continued after their
psychedelic origins were forgotten. Bergson saw the first movement of Hindus and
Greeks toward "dynamic religion" as associated with the "divine rapture" found
in intoxicating beverages; (5) more
recently Robert Graves, Gordon Wasson and Alan Watts have suggested that most
religions arose from such chemically-induced theophanies. Mary Barnard is the
most explicit proponent of this thesis. "Which... was more likely to happen
first," she asks in the autumn 1963 journal of Phi Beta Kappa: "the
spontaneously generated idea of an afterlife in which the disembodied soul,
liberated from the restrictions of time and space, experiences eternal bliss, or
the accidental discovery of hallucinogenic plants that give a sense of euphoria,
dislocate the center of consciousness, and distort time and space, making them
balloon outward in greatly expanded vistas?" Her own answer is that "the
[latter] experience might have had... an almost explosive effect on the largely
dormant minds of men, causing them to think of things they had never thought of
before. This, if you like, is direct revelation." Her use of the subjunctive
"might" renders this formulation of her answer equivocal, but she concludes her
essay on a note that is completely unequivocal: "Looking at the matter coldly,
unintoxicated and unentranced, I am willing to prophesy that fifty
theo-botanists working for fifty years would make the current theories
concerning the origins of much mythology and theology as out-of-date as
pre-Copernican astronomy." (6)
This is an important hypothesis one which must surely engage
the attention of historians of religion for some time to come. But as I am
concerned here only to spot the points at which the drugs erupt onto the field
of serious religious study, not to ride the geysers to whatever height, I shall
not pursue Miss Barnard's thesis. Having located what appears to be the crux of
the historical question, namely the extent to which drugs not merely duplicate
or simulate theologically sponsored experiences but generate or shape theologies
themselves, I turn to phenomenology.
2. Drugs and Religion Viewed Phenomenologically
Phenomenology attempts a careful description of human experience. The question
the drugs pose for the phenomenology of religion, therefore, is whether the
experiences they induce differ from religious experiences reached au nature and
if so how.
Even the Bible notes that chemically induced
psychic states bear some resemblance to religious ones. Peter had to
appeal to a circumstantial criterion the early hour of the day to defend those
who were caught up in the Pentecostal experience against the charge that they
were merely drunk: "These men are not drunk, as you suppose, since it is only
the third hour of the day" (Acts 2:15); and Paul initiates the comparison when
he admonishes the Ephesians not to "get drunk with wine... but [to] be filled
with the spirit" (Ephesians 5:18). Are such comparisons, paralleled in the
accounts of virtually every religion, superficial? How far can they be pushed?
Not all the way, students of religion have thus far insisted.
With respect to the new drugs, Professor R. C. Zaehner has drawn the line
emphatically. "The importance of Huxley's Doors of Perception," he
writes, "is that in it the author clearly makes the claim that what he
experienced under the influence of mescalin is closely comparable to a genuine
mystical experience. If he is right... the conclusions... are alarming." (7)
Zaehner thinks that Huxley is not right, but Zaehner is mistaken.
There are, of course, innumerable drug experiences which haven't a
religious feature; they can be sensual as readily as spiritual, trivial as
readily as transforming, capricious as readily as sacramental. If there is one
point about which every student of the drugs agrees, it is that there is no such
thing as the drug experience per se no experience which the drugs, as it were,
merely secrete. Every experience is a mix of three ingredients: drug, set (the
psychological makeup of the individual) and setting (the social and physical
environment in which it is taken). But given the right set and setting, the
drugs can induce religious experiences indistinguishable from ones that occur
spontaneously. Nor need set and setting be exceptional. The way the statistics
are currently running, it looks as if from one-fourth to one-third of the
general population will have religious experiences if they take the drugs under
naturalistic conditions, meaning by this conditions in which the researcher
supports the subject but doesn't try to influence the direction his experience
will take. Among subjects who have strong religious inclinations to begin with,
the proportion of those having religious experiences jumps to three-fourths. If
they take them in settings which are religious too, the ratio soars to nine out
of ten.
How do we know that the experiences these people have
really are religious? We can begin with the fact that they say they are. The
"one-fourth to one-third of the general populous" figure is drawn from two
sources. Ten months after they had had their experiences, 24 percent of the 194
subjects in a study by the California psychiatrist Oscar Janiger characterized
them as having been religious. (8)
Thirty-two percent of the 74 subjects in Ditman and Hayman's study reported that
in looking back on their LSD experience it looked as if it had been "very much"
or "quite a bit" a religious experience; 42 percent checked as true the
statement that they "were left with a greater awareness of God, or a higher
power, or ultimate reality." (9) The
statement that three-fourths of subjects having religious "sets" will have
religious experiences comes from the reports of sixty-nine religious
professionals who took the drugs while the Harvard project was in progress. (10)
In the absence of (a) a single definition of a religious
experience acceptable to psychologists of religion generally, and (b) foolproof
ways of ascertaining whether actual experiences exemplify any definition, I am
not sure there is a better way of telling whether the experiences of the 333 men
and women involved in the above studies were religious than by noting whether
they seemed so to them. But if more rigorous methods are preferred, they exist;
they have been utilized and confirm the conviction of the man in the street that
drug experiences can indeed be religious. In his doctoral study at Harvard
University, Dr. Walter Pahnke worked out a typology of religious experience (in
this instance of the mystical variety) based on the classic cases of mystical
experiences as summarized in Walter Stace's Mysticism and Philosophy. He
then administered psilocybin to ten theology students and professors in the
setting of a Good Friday service. The drug was given "double-blind," meaning
that neither Dr. Pahnke nor his subjects would know which ten were getting
psilocybin and which ten placebos to constitute a control group. Subsequently
the reports the subjects wrote of their experiences were laid successively
before three college-graduate housewives who, without being informed about the
nature of the study, were asked to rate each statement as to the degree (strong,
moderate, slight, or none) to which it exemplified each of the nine traits of
mystical experience as enumerated in the typology of mysticism worked out in
advance. When the test of significance was applied to their statistics, it
showed that "those subjects who received psilocybin experienced phenomena which
were indistinguishable from, if not identical with... the categories defined by
our typology of mysticism." (11)
With the thought that the reader might like to test his own
powers of discernment on the question being considered, I insert here a simple
test I gave to a group of Princeton students following a recent discussion
sponsored by the Woodrow Wilson Society.
Below are accounts of two religious experiences.
One occurred under the influence of drugs, one without their influence. Check
the one you think was drug-induced.
I
Suddenly I burst into a vast, new, indescribably
wonderful universe. Although I am writing this over a year later, the thrill
of the surprise and amazement, the awesomeness of the revelation, the
engulfment in an overwhelming feeling-wave of gratitude and blessed
wonderment, are as fresh, and the memory of the experience is as vivid, as if
it had happened five minutes ago. And yet to concoct anything by way of
description that would even hint at the magnitude, the sense of ultimate
reality... this seems such an impossible task. The knowledge which has infused
and affected every aspect of my life came instantaneously and with such
complete force of certainty that it was impossible, then or since, to doubt
its validity.
II
All at once, without warning of any kind, I
found myself wrapped in a flame-colored cloud. For an instant I thought of
fire... the next, I knew that the fire was within myself. Directly afterward
there came upon me a sense of exultation, of immense joyousness accompanied or
immediately followed by an intellectual illumination impossible to describe.
Among other things, I did not merely come to believe, but I saw that the
universe is not composed of dead matter, but is, on the contrary, a living
Presence; I became conscious in myself of eternal life.... I saw that all men
are immortal: that the cosmic order is such that without any peradventure all
things work together for the good of each and all; that the foundation
principle of the world... is what we call love, and that the happiness of each
and all is in the long run absolutely certain.
On
the occasion referred to, twice the number of students (46) answered incorrectly
as answered correctly (23). I bury the correct answer in a footnote to preserve
the reader's opportunity to test himself. (l2)
Why, in the face of this considerable evidence, does Zaehner
hold that drug experiences cannot be authentically religious? There appear to be
three reasons:
1. His own experience was "utterly trivial."
This of course proves that not all drug experiences are religious; it does not
prove that no drug experiences are religious.
2. He thinks
that the experiences of others which appear to be religious to them are not
truly so. Zaehner distinguishes three kinds of mysticism: nature mysticism in
which the soul is united with the natural world; monistic mysticism in which the
soul merges with an impersonal absolute; and theism in which the soul confronts
the living, personal God. He concedes that drugs can induce the first two
species of mysticism, but not its supreme instance, the theistic. As proof, he
analyzes Huxley's experience as recounted in The Doors of Perception to
show that it produced at best a blend of nature and monistic mysticism. Even if
we were to accept Zaehner's evaluation of the three forms of mysticism, Huxley's
case, and indeed Zaehner's entire book, would prove only that not every mystical
experience induced by the drugs is theistic. Insofar as Zaehner goes beyond this
to imply that drugs do not and cannot induce theistic mysticism, he not only
goes beyond the evidence but proceeds in the face of it. Professor Slotkin
reports that the peyote Indians "see visions, which may be of Christ Himself.
Sometimes they hear the voice of the Great Spirit. Sometimes they become aware
of the presence of God and of those personal shortcomings which must be
corrected if they are to do His will." (l3)
And G. M. Carstairs, reporting on the use of psychedelic bhang (marijuana) in
India, quotes a Brahmin as saying, "It gives good bhakti.... You get a very good
bhakti with bhang," bhakti being precisely Hinduism's theistic variant. (l4)
3. There is a third reason why Professor Zaehner might doubt
that drugs can induce experiences that are genuinely mystical. Professor Zaehner
is a Roman Catholic, and Roman Catholic doctrine teaches that mystical rapture
is a gift of grace and as such can never be reduced to man's control. This may
be true; certainly the empirical evidence cited does not preclude the
possibility of a genuine ontological or theological difference between natural
and drug-induced religious experiences. At this point, however, we are
considering phenomenology rather than ontology, description rather than
interpretation, and on this level there is no difference. Descriptively, drug
experiences cannot be distinguished from their natural religious counterpart.
When the current philosophical authority on mysticism, Dr. W. T. Stace,
Professor Emeritus at Princeton University, was asked whether the drug
experience is similar to the mystical experience, he answered, "It's not a
matter of its being similar to mystical experience; it is mystical
experience."
What we seem to be witnessing in Zaehner's
Mysticism Sacred and Profane is a reenactment of the age-old pattern in
the conflict between science and religion. Whenever a new controversy arises,
religion's first impulse is to deny the disturbing evidence science has
produced. Seen in perspective, Zaehner's refusal to admit that drugs can induce
experiences descriptively indistinguishable from those which are spontaneously
religious is the current counterpart of the seventeenth century theologians'
refusal to look through Galileo's telescope or, when they did, their persistence
in dismissing what they saw as machinations of the devil. When the fact that
drugs can trigger religious experiences becomes incontrovertible, discussion
will move to the more difficult question of how this new fact is to be
interpreted. The latter question leads beyond phenomenology into philosophy.
3. Drugs and Religion Viewed Philosophically
Why do
people reject evidence? Because they find it threatening, we may suppose.
Theologians are not the only professionals to utilize this mode of defense. In
his Personal Knowledge, Michael Polanyi recounts the way the medical
profession ignored such palpable facts as the painless amputation of human
limbs, performed before their own eyes in hundreds of successive cases,
concluding that the subjects were impostors who were either deluding their
physician or colluding with him. One physician, Esdaile, carried out about 300
major operations painlessly under mesmeric trance in India, but neither in India
nor in Great Britain could he get medical journals to print accounts of his
work. Polanyi attributes this closed-mindedness to "lack of a conceptual
framework in which their discoveries could be separated from specious and
untenable admixtures."
The "untenable admixture" in the fact
that psychotomimetic drugs can induce religious experience is their apparent
implicate: that religious disclosures are no more veridical than psychotic ones.
For religious skeptics, this conclusion is obviously not untenable at all; it
fits in beautifully with their thesis that all religion is at heart an
escape from reality. Psychotics avoid reality by retiring into dream worlds of
make-believe; what better evidence that religious visionaries do the same than
the fact that identical changes in brain chemistry produces both states of mind?
Had not Marx already warned us that religion is the "opiate" of the people?
Apparently he was more literally accurate than he supposed. Freud was likewise
too mild. He "never doubted that religious phenomena are to be understood only
on the model of the neurotic symptoms of the individual." (15) He
should have said "psychotic symptoms."
So the religious
skeptic is likely to reason. What about the religious believer? Convinced that
religious experiences are not fundamentally delusory, can he admit that
psychotomimetic drugs can occasion them? To do so he needs (to return to
Polanyi's words) "a conceptual framework in which [the discoveries can] be
separated from specious and untenable admixtures," the latter being in this case
the conclusion that religious experiences are in general delusory.
One way to effect the separation would be to argue that despite
phenomenological similarities between natural and drug-induced religious
experiences, they are separated by a crucial ontological difference. Such
an argument would follow the pattern of theologians who argue for the "real
presence" of Christ's body and blood in the bread and wine of the Eucharist
despite their admission that chemical analysis, confined as it is to the level
of "accidents" rather than "essences," would not disclose this presence. But
this distinction will not appeal to many today, for it turns on an
essence-accident metaphysics which is not widely accepted. Instead of fighting a
rear-guard action by insisting that if drug and non-drug religious experiences
can't be distinguished empirically there must be some trans-empirical factor
which distinguishes them and renders the drug experience profane, I wish to
explore the possibility of accepting drug-induced experiences as religious in
every sense of the word without relinquishing confidence in the truth claims of
religious experience generally.
To begin with the weakest of
all arguments, the argument from authority: William James didn't discount his
insights which occurred while his brain chemistry was altered. The paragraph
in which he retrospectively evaluates his nitrous oxide experiences has become
classic, but it is so pertinent to the present discussion that it merits quoting
again.
One conclusion was forced upon my mind at that
time, and my impression of its truth has ever since remained unshaken. It is
that our normal waking consciousness, rational consciousness as we call it, is
but one special type of consciousness, whilst all about it, parted from it by
the filmiest of screens, there lie potential forms of consciousness entirely
different. We may go through life without suspecting their existence; but
apply the requisite stimulus, and at a touch they are there in all their
completeness, definite types of mentality which probably somewhere have their
field of application and adaptation. No account of the universe in its
totality can be final which leaves these other forms of consciousness quite
disregarded. How to regard them is the question—for they are so discontinuous
with ordinary consciousness. Yet they may determine attitudes though they
cannot furnish formulas, and open a region though they fail to give a map. At
any rate, they forbid a premature closing of our accounts with reality.
Looking back on my own experiences, they all converge toward a kind of insight
to which I cannot help ascribing some metaphysical significance. (16)
To this argument from authority, I add two that
try to provide something by way of reasons. Drug experiences that assume a
religious cast tend to have fearful and/or beatific features, and each of my
hypotheses relates to one of these aspects of the experience.
Beginning with the ominous, "fear of the Lord," awe-ful features, Gordon Wasson,
the New York banker-turned-mycologist, describes these as he encountered them in
his psilocybin experience as follows: "Ecstasy! In common parlance... ecstasy is
fun.... But ecstasy is not fun. Your very soul is seized and shaken until it
tingles. After all, who will choose to feel undiluted awe...? The unknowing
vulgar abuse the word; we must recapture its full and terrifying sense."
Emotionally the drug experience can be like having forty-foot waves crash over
you for several hours while you cling desperately to a life raft which may be
swept from under you at any minute. It seems quite possible that such an ordeal,
like any experience of a close call, could awaken rather fundamental sentiments
respecting life and death and destiny and trigger the "no atheists in foxholes"
effect. Similarly, as the subject emerges from the trauma and realizes that he
is not going to be insane as he had feared, there may come over him an
intensified appreciation like that frequently reported by patients recovering
from critical illness. "It happened on the day when my bed was pushed out of
doors to the open gallery of the hospital," reads one such report.
I cannot now recall whether the revelation came
suddenly or gradually; I only remember finding myself in the very midst of
those wonderful moments, beholding life for the first time in all its young
intoxication of loveliness, in its unspeakable joy, beauty, and importance. I
cannot say exactly what the mysterious change was. I saw no new thing, but I
saw all the usual things in a miraculous new light—in what I believe is their
true light. I saw for the first time how wildly beautiful and joyous, beyond
any words of mine to describe, is the whole of life. Every human being moving
across that porch, every sparrow that flew, every branch tossing in the wind,
was caught in and was a part of the whole mad ecstasy of loveliness, of joy,
of importance, of intoxication of life. (17)
If we do not discount religious intuitions
because they are prompted by battlefields and physical crises; if we
regard the latter as "calling us to our senses" more often than they seduce us
into delusions, need comparable intuitions be discounted simply because the
crises that trigger them are of an inner, psychic variety?
Turning from the hellish to the heavenly aspects of the drug experience,
some of the latter may be explainable by the hypothesis just stated; that
is, they may be occasioned by the relief that attends the sense of escape from
high danger. But this hypothesis cannot possibly account for all the
beatific episodes for the simple reason that the positive episodes often come
first, or to persons who experience no negative episodes whatever. Dr. Sanford
Unger of the National Institute of Mental Health reports that among his subjects
"50 to 60 percent will not manifest any real disturbance worthy of discussion,"
yet "around 75" will have at least one episode in which exaltation, rapture, and
joy are the key descriptions. (18)
How are we to account for the drug's capacity to induce peak experiences, such
as the following, which are not preceded by fear?
A feeling of great peace and contentment seemed
to flow through my entire body. All sound ceased and I seemed to be floating
in a great, very very still void or hemisphere. It is impossible to describe
the overpowering feeling of peace, contentment, and being a part of goodness
itself that I felt. I could feel my body dissolving and actually becoming a
part of the goodness and peace that was all around me. Words can't describe
this. I feel an awe and wonder that such a feeling could have occurred to
me. (19)
Consider the following line of argument. Like
every other form of life, man's nature has become distinctive through
specialization. Man has specialized in developing a cerebral cortex. The
analytic powers of this instrument are a standing wonder, but it seems less able
to provide man with the sense that he is meaningfully related to his
environment, to life, the world and history in their wholeness. As Albert Camus
describes the situation, "If I were... a cat among animals, this life would have
a meaning, or rather this problem would not arise, for I should belong to this
world. I would be this world to which I am now opposed by my whole
consciousness." (20)
Note that it is Camus' consciousness that opposes him to his world. The drugs do
not knock this consciousness out, but while they leave it operative they also
activate areas of the brain that normally lie below its threshold of awareness.
One of the clearest objective signs that the drugs are taking effect is the
dilation they produce in the pupils of the eyes, while one of the most
predictable subjective signs is the intensification of visual perception. Both
of these responses are controlled by portions of the brain that lie deep,
further to the rear than the mechanisms that govern consciousness. Meanwhile we
know that the human organism is interlaced with its world in innumerable ways it
normally cannot sense through gravitational fields, body respiration, and the
like; the list could be multiplied until man's skin began to seem more like a
thoroughfare than a boundary. Perhaps the deeper regions of the brain which
evolved earlier and are more like those of the lower animals "If I were... a
cat.. . I should belong to this world" can sense this relatedness better than
can the cerebral cortex which now dominates our awareness. If so, when the drugs
rearrange the neurohumors that chemically transmit impulses across synapses
between neurons, man's consciousness and his submerged, intuitive, ecological
awareness might for a spell become interlaced. This is, of course, no more than
a hypothesis, but how else are we to account for the extraordinary incidence
under the drugs of that kind of insight the keynote of which James described as
invariably a reconciliation. It is as if the
opposites of the world, whose contradictoriness and conflict make all our
difficulties and troubles, were melted into one and the same genus, but one of
the species, the nobler and better one, is itself the genus, and so soaks up
and absorbs its opposites into itself. (21)
4. The Drugs and Religion Viewed "Religiously"
Suppose
that drugs can induce experiences that are indistinguishable from religious
ones, and that we can respect their reports. Do they shed any light, not (we now
ask) on life, but on the nature of the religious life?
One
thing they may do is throw religious experience itself into perspective by
clarifying its relation to the religious life as a whole. Drugs appear able to
induce religious experiences; it is less evident that they can produce religious
lives. It follows that religion is more than religious experiences. This is
hardly news, but it may be a useful reminder, especially to those who incline
toward "the religion of religious experience," which is to say toward lives bent
on the acquisition of desired states of experience irrespective of their
relation to life's other demands and components.
Despite the
dangers of faculty psychology, it remains useful to regard man as having a mind,
a will, and feelings. One of the lessons of religious history is that to be
adequate a faith must rouse and involve all three components of man's nature.
Religions of reason grow arid; religions of duty, leaden. Religions of
experience have their comparable pitfalls, as evidenced by Taoism's struggle
(not always successful) to keep from degenerating into quietism, and the
vehemence with which Zen Buddhism has insisted that once students have attained
satori, they must be driven out of it, back into the world. The case of
Zen is especially pertinent here, for it pivots on an enlightenment
experience satori or kensho which some (but not all) Zennists says
resembles LSD. Alike or different, the point is that Zen recognizes that unless
the experience is joined to discipline, it will come to naught.
Even the Buddha... had to sit.... Without
joriki, the particular power developed through zazen [seated
meditation], the vision of oneness attained in enlightenment ... in time
becomes clouded and eventually fades into a pleasant memory instead of
remaining an omnipresent reality shaping our daily life.... To be able to live
in accordance with what the Mind's eye has revealed through satori requires,
like the purification of character and the development of personality, a
ripening period of zazen. (22)
If the religion of religious experience is a
snare and a delusion, it follows that no religion that fixes its faith primarily
in substances that induce religious experiences can be expected to come to a
good end. What promised to be a shortcut will prove to be a short circuit; what
began as a religion will end as a religion surrogate. Whether chemical
substances can be helpful adjuncts to faith is another question. The
peyote-using Native American Church seems to indicate that they can be;
anthropologists give this church a good report, noting among other things that
members resist alcohol and alcoholism better than do non-members. (23)
The conclusion to which evidence currently points would seem to be that
chemicals can aid the religious life, but only where set within a context of
faith (meaning by this the conviction that what they disclose is true) and
discipline (meaning diligent exercise of the will in the attempt to work out the
implications of the disclosures for the living of life in the every day, common
sense world).
Nowhere today in Western civilization are these
two conditions jointly fulfilled. Churches lack faith in the sense just
mentioned, hipsters lack discipline. This might lead us to forget about the
drugs, were it not for one fact: the distinctive religious emotion and the one
drugs unquestionably can occasion Otto's mysterium tremendum, majestas,
mysterium fascinans; in a phrase, the phenomenon of religious awe seems to
be declining sharply. As Paul Tillich said in an address to the Hillel Society
at Harvard several years ago:
The question our century puts before us [is]: Is
it possible to regain the lost dimension, the encounter with the Holy, the
dimension which cuts through the world of subjectivity and objectivity and
goes down to that which is not world but is the mystery of the Ground of
Being?
Tillich may be right; this may be the
religious question of our century. For if (as we have insisted) religion cannot
be equated with religious experience, neither can it long survive its absence.
References
1. Soundings: Essays
Concerning Christian Understandings, edited by A. R. Vidler. Cambridge: The
University Press, 1962, The statement cited appears on page 72. (back)
2. Hamilton, Edith. Mythology.
New York, Mentor Book, 1940, p. 55. (back)
3. Quoted in Alan Watts, The Spirit
of Zen. New York: Grove Press, 1958, p. 110. (back)
4. Mylonas, George. Eleusis and the
Eleusinian Mysteries. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1961, p.
284. (back)
5. Two Sources of Morality and
Religion. New York: Henry Holt and Co., 1935, pp. 206-212. (back)
6. "The God in the Flowerpot." The
American Scholar (Autumn 1963), pp. 584, 586. (back)
7. Mysticism, Sacred and Profane.
New York: Oxford Galaxy Book, 1961, p. 12. (back)
8. Quoted in McGlothlin, William H.
"Long-lasting Effects of LSD on Certain Attitudes in Normals." Printed for
private distribution by the RAND Corporation, p. 16. (back)
9. Ibid., pp. 45, 46. (back)
10. Leary, Timothy. "The Religious
Experience: Its Production and Interpretation." The Psychedelic Review,
vol. I, no. 3 (1964), p. 325. (back)
11. "Drugs and Mysticism: An Analysis
of the Relationship Between Psychedelic Drugs and the Mystical Consciousness." A
thesis presented to the Committee on Higher Degrees in History and Philosophy of
Religion, Harvard University, June 1963. (back)
12. The first account is quoted
anonymously in "The Issue of the Consciousness-Expanding Drugs." Main
Currents in Modern Thought vol. XX, no. I (September-October 1963), pp.
10-11. The second experience was that of Dr. R. M. Bucke, the author of
Cosmic Consciousness, as quoted in James, William. The Varieties of
Religious Experience. New York: The Modern Library, 1902, pp. 390391. The
former experience occurred under the influence of drugs, the latter did not. (back)
13. Slotkin, James S. Peyote
Religion. Glencoe, III.: Free Press, 1956. (back)
14. "Daru and Bhang." Quarterly
Journal of the Study of Alcohol. 1954, 15:229. (back)
15. Totem and Taboo. New York:
Modern Library, 1938. (back)
16. The Varieties of Religious
Experience, op. cit., pp. 378-379. (back)
17. Montague, Margaret Prescott.
Twenty Minutes of Reality. Saint Paul, Minn.: Macalester Park Publishing
Company, 1947, pp. 15, 17. (back)
18. "The Current Scientific Status of
Psychedelic Drug Research." A paper read at the Conference on Methods in
Philosophy and the Sciences, New School for Social Research, May 3, 1964. (back)
19. Quoted by Dr. Unger in the paper
just mentioned. (back)
20. The Myth of Sisyphus. New
York: Vintage, 1955, p. 38. (back)
21. James, William, op. cit., p.
379. (back)
22. Kapleau, Philip. Zen Practice
and Attainment. A manuscript in process of publication. (back)
23. Slotkin, James S., op. cit.
(back)